Brian Greene's 'The Elegant Universe'
[Quantum
mechanics] describes nature as absurd from the point of view of common
sense. And it fully agrees with
experiment. So I hope you can accept
nature as She is—absurd.
~Richard
Feynman (quoted in Brian Greene, The
Elegant Universe)
When
studying literature and science, it’s not always clear what exactly we’re
talking about. Are we discussing
scientific topics in fictional narratives, or the way that narrativization can
help us understand science… or both? Or
are we discussing something less unidirectional? Do science and literature share isomorphic
patterns of behavior and organization?
Do they intersect with one another, culturally and socially speaking? Might they even illuminate various qualities
of the other, offering insightful ways to understand their parallel
developments? Personally speaking, I
don’t think that “literature and science” means any one methodology or
approach, but a host of perspectives on what humanities academics call cultural production—that is, modes of inscription
that contribute to how we know the world around us, as Pierre Bourdieu explored
in The Field of Cultural Production.
For
example, take a famous principle of twentieth-century physics: Werner
Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle. Now
a staple of quantum mechanics and central to our understanding of the universe,
the uncertainty principle asserts that reality, at the level of quanta (the
microscopically small), is indeterminate.
Subatomic particles cannot be described as having both determinate speed
and being in a determinate place. This
is not a limitation on our observational capacities, but an apparently
fundamental characteristic of reality according to experimental results. In a realistic sense, the uncertainty
principle describes something wholly non-textual: the fabric of reality. But “uncertainty” is not available in nature,
as it were; it’s our concept for framing what we observe at the quantum
level. In other words, it’s a mode of
inscription—a narrative—that produces knowledge about something.
I’ve
been thinking more about the relationship between literature and science lately
while reading Brian Greene’s The Elegant
Universe, which might be the most exciting scientific text I’ve come across
in a while. I always love reading about
“weird science,” and nothing gets much weirder than theoretical physics. Greene narrates the shifts from Newtonian
physics to relativity to quantum mechanics and beyond with ease and clarity,
and his creative examples are particularly helpful (not to mention
entertaining). But what caught my eye
was a particular analogy in his explanation of Richard Feynman’s interpretation
of the famous double-slit experiment, in which a beam of light fired at a
photographic plate must pass through a barrier with two slits in it. According to classical physics, the
photographic plate should reflect two steady columns of light corresponding to
the two slits; but instead, the light particles behave as waves, producing an
interference pattern that splays several columns out across the plate. Feynman’s contribution to this multifaceted
experiment was that not only do the light particles (specifically, electrons) behave
as waves, and not only do they just go through one slit—in fact, they pass
through both slits; what’s more, he
proposed that the electrons fired at the photographic plate traverse “every possible trajectory simultaneously.”
According
to Feynman, the electrons in the double-slit experiment travel—impossibly, it
would seem—an unfathomable number of paths: through the left slit, through the
right, into your neighbor’s bathroom, and to the edge of the Oort Cloud. In fact, the particles of all matter, Feynman
theorized, are constantly pursuing all imaginable paths simultaneously. So how do objects such as tables, cars,
buildings, and human beings, hang together if our electrons are popping to vast
reaches of the galaxy? Feynman suggested
that in large objects, the immense multitude of paths cancel each other out—except for one. And that path is the path the object takes:
your commute to work, the plane from New York to Los Angeles, the apple that,
as legend has it, fell on Newton’s head.
In this way, quantum weirdness is brought in line with Newtonian physics
(at least to an extent). At this point,
Greene offers the following analogy:
Just as
we may find that varying interpretations of a book or a film can be more or
less helpful in aiding our understanding of different aspects of the work, the
same is true of the different approaches to quantum mechanics.
I appreciate this example for
its perceptive alignment of the sciences and the humanities. The humanities, like the sciences, offer
perspectives on various problems. Some
perspectives will end up being more helpful than others, and discourse rewards
these perspectives. The perfect
understanding of a problem doesn’t emerge out of one interpretation, but from a constantly recombining multitude.
Although
largely about the many avenues of string theory, Greene spends the first
hundred pages or so documenting the shifts from Newtonian mechanics to physics
today (or 1999, when The Elegant Universe
was published). This framework offers
readers the advantage of witnessing scientific revolution in the making, as
described formally by Thomas Kuhn in The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
In other words, the shift from Newtonian mechanics to string theory
shouldn’t be thought of as progress,
in the sense that older models are replaced with newer ones. As Greene and other physicists emphasize,
Newton’s calculations haven’t been abandoned; they’ve simply been expanded upon
and refined. His observations and
proposals about gravity are still crucial to the enterprise, but they’re
incomplete without the also crucial components of relativity, quantum
indeterminacy, supersymmetry, and others.
In
addition to the specifics of these various theories, The Elegant Universe is about how different theories fit
together. Thus far, every explanation of
the workings of the universe leaves gaps, fissures, aporias of logic. Take the example of quantum tunneling: the prospect that particles might temporarily
“borrow” enough energy to actually penetrate, or “tunnel,” through solid
barriers. Theoretically speaking, it’s
not entirely impossible (albeit highly unlikely, since it would require all composite
particles to tunnel at the same time) that a tennis ball might pass right
through your racket without damaging it.
After tunneling, the particle returns the energy it borrowed—no harm, no
foul. There is no logical framework for
how the energy transfer occurs, and Greene compares it to loaning money; it’s
established on trust and uncertainty. Such
possibilities seem to conflict with older models, even leading Albert Einstein
to say that “God does not play dice with the Universe.” As physicists worked to introduce quantum
mechanics to relativity theory, some inconsistencies were explained; but others
were revealed. Over time, science has
remained a process of creative recombination, reconfiguration, and re-narrativization.
To return to Greene’s metaphor, science
is comprised of different ways to interpret the text.
According
to literary critic N. Katherine Hayles, Niels Bohr—an important figure in the
Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics—was fond of saying that human
beings are “suspended in language.” Like
the raw matter of the universe, language can be tested; we can experiment with
it, and we can try out various hypotheses concerning its meanings. It’s sometimes objected that these kinds of
arguments are less important than scientific ones, and usually this objection
has to do with the relevance of science, or some such. Yet the experimental trials and tribulations
of physics don’t test the ordinary experience of daily life as enjoyed by the
vast majority of humanity. They test a
narrow range of experience that nonetheless serves as the foundation for all
life—human and nonhuman (as far as we know).
Likewise, the testing of narrative meaning speaks to a narrow range of
experimental language; but it’s from the confusions illuminated by these tests
that our ordinary language arises. I
find Greene’s comparison of scientific interpretations to literary
interpretations compelling because it accounts for the analogous structures of
discourse and argument that underlie both fields. We have a great deal to learn about
literature by studying scientific inscription; and we have a great deal to
learn about science by studying literary experimentation.
Comments
Post a Comment