Between Facts and Narratives
We are suspended in language in such a
way that we cannot say what is up and what is down. The word “reality” is also a word, a word
which we must learn to use correctly.
—Niels Bohr
As long as we stick to things and words
we can believe that we are speaking of what we see, that we see what we are
speaking of, and that the two are linked.
—Gilles Deleuze
In a recent interview with Dave
Rubin, Milo Yiannopoulos objected to what he perceives as the “sloppy,
ideological reporting” from left-wing journalists who champion progressive
ideals. Yiannopoulos went on to associate
this kind of journalism with the “brazen untruths” and “major plagiarism
scandals” that he claims also mostly come from the left, and summed up the
reason for this association in a single comment: “They believe in narrative
over facts.”
This is the Gradgrind mentality, for fans of Charles Dickens: “You can only form the minds of reasoning animals upon Facts: nothing else will ever be of any service to them.” Anyone who spends enough time
reading right-wing forums or chatrooms, blogs, tweets, etc. knows that those
who subscribe to this general mentality proclaim their
intellectual superiority through recourse to fact-based knowledge, rationality,
logic, objectivity… a host of terms that have trickled down to non-experts,
primarily through so-called pundits such as Yiannopoulos, Ben Shapiro, Tucker
Carlson, and others: “These words are usually used interchangeably and without
regard to their proper usage,” writes Aisling McCrea, “squished together in a
vague Play-Doh ball of smug superiority, to be thrown wherever possible at
their ‘emotional’ and ‘irrational’ enemies: feminists, Marxists, liberals,
SJWs, and definitely the feminist Marxist liberal SJWs.” The opposition here is between the rational
right and the irrational left, almost always identified with the academic left
(a homogenous suite, apparently—I’m sure Noam Chomsky would disagree), whom the
right accuses of peddling not facts, but narratives:
presumably false stories or expressions of social reality that lack the facts necessary for backing them up.
Despite its centrality in
contemporary political debates (if they can be called debates), this
distinction between facts and narratives isn’t new. In a very strong sense, it can be traced back
to C.P. Snow’s influential 1959 lecture, The Two Cultures. For Snow, intellectual
society found itself, in the mid-twentieth century, divided into two camps: the
sciences and the humanities. A scientist
himself, Snow accused those in the humanities—whom he referred to as “literary
intellectuals”—of being largely ignorant of scientific matters, and of being
unable to properly engage with scientific discourse. Scientists, on the other hand, expressed
admiration for (and, more importantly, an understanding of) the liberal arts. Snow’s argument wasn’t that literature was
less important than science, although some may read such sentiment into his
lament; rather, he argued that there was a disparity in education between
scholars in the sciences and those in the humanities: “So the great edifice of
modern physics goes up,” he writes, “and the majority of the cleverest
people in the western world have about as much insight into it as
their Neolithic ancestors would have had.”
Objections aside, Snow’s position is
not an explicitly antagonistic one (although it is, perhaps, a presumptuous
one; informed dialogues between the arts and life sciences were in fact a
central aspect of intellectual life at Cambridge University in the 1920s and
‘30s). As Steven Meyer writes, “Snow
himself came to regret the sharpness of the division, even proposing a third
culture, sociological in nature, to bridge it.”
This proposal anticipated the rise of science studies, a primarily
sociological perspective on scientific development that paid attention to how
science approached, observed, and represented its findings. A burst of publications in the philosophy and
history of science followed Snow’s lecture, including Thomas Kuhn’s monumental The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
(1962), Paul Feyerabend’s Against Method
(1975), and Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar’s Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts
(1979). At this point, things begin to
look murky, especially from the position of those who champion facts and
rationality. Their objection lies at the
heart of much political disagreement today: how
can facts be constructed? For those
in the humanities, this usually isn’t even a question. The social construction of facts is simply a
given. And yet Latour and Woolgar
themselves expressed some retrospective regret over their choice of subtitle,
and even eventually removed the word “social” (not that this assuaged those who
object to the construction of facts in any sense).
Latour and Woolgar describe the
construction of a fact as a difficult process to comprehend for the
not-so-simple reason that it involves the decontextualization of the fact. In other words, the fact loses “all
historical reference.” It becomes (or
appears as) an abstract, valueless contingency of the universe, rendered
effectively meaningless. To examine how facts
assume the appearance of objective, ahistorical entities, Latour and Woolgar
focus on the existence of the thyrotropin-releasing factor, or TRF,
demonstrating that its emergence as a fact depended not on its ahistorical
existence (whatever the factor might be regardless of history) but on the
subfields and disciplines that informed the approaches to the uncertain
possibility of TRF—specifically, biochemistry and neuroendocrinology. It’s beside the point that what we call TRF
exists beyond human observation (that is, it’s there whether we observe it or
not). The point is that its existence
can only be framed and expressed in the languages of particular discourses, or
what Latour and Woolgar call the “literary inscription” of laboratory work. In effect, what these sociologists of science
did was unveil the narrative of a
fact’s emergence.
It’s no surprise that natural
scientists don’t look kindly on this assessment of their work, and their
resistance has proven detrimental to the sociological enterprise. Looking back, Latour and Woolgar’s study is
viewed as a seminal publication in the history of a particular brand of
intellectual discourse that was awarded several names: most familiar are
constructivism, relativism, and postmodernism.
The most naïve misunderstanding of the discourse that these names tend
to stand in for is that they reject reality altogether, a position that is proven
false by even a mildly close reading of Laboratory
Life. I doubt many committed
scientists take this position. Rather,
theirs is a more nuanced objection, and appears to derive from the impression
that if facts are socially constructed (or even just constructed) then they
can’t be useful; but this isn’t what Latour and Woolgar claim either. To the contrary, they readily admit the
usefulness of scientific facts. They
merely object to their necessity. Addressing Roger Guillemin’s decision to
approach the existence of TRF via its hormonal structure, they write that
“[b]ecause of the success of his strategy, there is a tendency to think of
Guillemin’s decision as having been the only correct one to make. But the
decision to reshape the field was not logically necessary. Even if the decision to pursue the structure
of TRF(H) had not been taken, a subfield of releasing factors would still
exist.” In other words, if Guillemin
hadn’t approached TRF in the way he did, another possible approach could have
been equally (if not more) successful in bringing its existence to light.
It’s only in retrospect that such
decisions appear necessary—that is, they couldn’t have happened any other
way. It is, and has been, one of the
central concerns (I would venture to call it an imperative) of the humanities
to reveal the inaccuracy of this notion.
To many intellectuals today, this point is usually viewed one of two
ways: a) absolutely, things could have happened any number of ways—right on!
and b) absolutely, things could have happened any number of ways—who
cares? To those in the second camp, the
contingency imperative feels old, tired, dated.
It no longer tells us anything new.
And to an extent, they’re correct.
Within academia, the knowledge and understanding of historical
circumstance and contingency is quite extensive, and objections to it often
rest firmly on what might be called pragmatic grounds: But
things did happen this way, and so
this is the way the world is. For some in
the humanities, this constitutes a dangerous position because it’s seen as
enabling and naturalizing a hierarchical view of social organization, despite
the fact that those who maintain this position fully admit historical
contingency. For others, this position
is less dangerous than it is restrictive.
If we acquiesce too easily to the situation as is, then we risk missing
out on the possibility of ameliorating circumstances (this might be seen as a
less radical version of Feyerabend’s argument in Against Method, in which he promotes an “anything goes” approach to
scientific practice).
Yet for others, the “things happened
this way” crowd simply reinforces the aspect of facticity that Latour and
Woolgar find disturbing: the wiping away of history. The push to ignore how things happened
contains an implicit rhetorical move to treat historical circumstances as
abstract, ahistorical things—cold, hard facts. Thus, when this rhetoric trickles down into
the corridors and forums of the internet, users latch onto the facticity of
things without regard for their constitutive narratological basis: their
constitution (or construction, if you like) through narrative. Absent narrative, facts are meaningless. Even worse, they’re entirely imperceptible in
any impactful sense. We have facts because we have narratives—not the other
way around. We treat gravity as a fact
because we know what happens when someone falls from a high place; we treat the
human respiratory system as a fact because we know what happens when someone
tries to breathe underwater. These are
real occurrences, but they become facts
because the occurrences mean something.
They serve a narrative purpose in our lives.
Put another way, there’s no such
thing as a fact that isn’t narratively inflected. This isn’t to say that narratives can’t be
damaging, or that the material basis of facts—the world we inhabit—somehow
doesn’t exist. There is a way to read
the current political fetishism of facts as a reaction to perceived left-wing
impressions that the lives and experiences of a significant portion of Western
individuals aren’t real in any substantive sense. The result is an instinctive attraction to
the solidity of facts as affirmation of one’s livelihood. Yet the difference between these two camps
isn’t a belief in facts; rather, it’s what each side takes facts to be.
The facts-over-narratives camp takes facts to be autonomous. Paul Feyerabend calls this the autonomy
principle: the assertion “that the facts which belong to the empirical content
of some theory are available whether or not one considers alternatives to this theory.” Feyerabend’s critique of the autonomy
principle is a variation on Latour and Woolgar’s idea of social construction;
for Feyerabend, the theoretical underpinnings of facts make them potentially
invisible when observed through alternative theoretical frameworks.
Feyerabend’s anarchic approach
(which he wouldn’t call a methodology) aims to diminish the unspoken mythic
status of facts. He argues that
entertaining other methods—even seemingly absurd methods—can illuminate facts
that would otherwise go unnoticed. Although
Feyerabend’s thesis may apply to some facts, it’s doubtful whether it applies
to all of them; that is, some facts most certainly transcend the frontiers of
theoretical discipline. Perhaps a more
compelling argument is to be found in Niels Bohr’s philosophy-physics, which
call into question a host of assumptions involving our instrumental capacity to
know the world around us, as articulated by Karen Barad:
·
A belief
in representationalism (the independently determined existence of words and
things)
·
The
metaphysics of individualism (that the world is composed of individual entities
with individually determined boundaries and properties)
·
And the
intrinsic separability of knower and known (that measurements reveal the
preexisting values of the properties of independently existing objects as
separate from the measuring agencies)
The
emphasis of these points, as Barad explains, is their challenge to the
subsistence of facts. Facts don’t exist
in a vacuum; they’re shaped by the instruments, strategies, and theories that
isolate them. Returning to Latour and
Woolgar, it isn’t necessary that a fact’s emergence be tied to the theoretical
apparatus that identified it; but that doesn’t mean the fact remains the same regardless
of the apparatus. For example, the thing
that Latour and Woolgar discuss as TRF was debated among scientists:
what some deciphered as the thyrotropin-releasing factor others suggested should be called the thyrotropin-releasing hormone.
This disagreement reflects the varying methodologies by which scientists
approached their object of study.
In other words, what we take to be
facts don’t necessarily mirror the world prior to our articulation of the world
in terms of facts. Facts only appear to
us because they fit into a preconceived narrative. Again, this doesn’t mean that entities in the
world don’t exist or that facts, narratively conceived though they may be, aren’t
useful. The problem I’m focusing on here
emerges when people try to separate narratives from facts, as though this
itself is a categorical distinction in the world. Facts only appear as such to those with a
vested interest in making them independent of narratives—because this is how we
absolve ourselves of prejudice. If facts
preexist our discovery of them, then they can’t be shaped theoretically; they’re
simply a part of the world, out there for our observation. But facts only come into being through our preconceptions. They only manifest meaningfully against the
backdrop of a theory.
Two possible objections, by way of
conclusion:
1. Isn’t it possible to stumble upon a
fact accidentally?
a. Counterintuitive answer: No, because to discover a fact means
that one must already be looking for it.
We can stumble upon anomalies—but anomalies aren’t facts, although they
may eventually become facts. Prior to
sufficient theorization (or narrativization), anomalous aspects of the world
are not facts, but gaps in knowledge.
2. Aren’t you posing the entanglement of
facts and narratives as a fact?
a. Intuitive answer: Yes, but as a fact like all others—that is, a fact bound to a
particular narrative approach. And as I’ve
already said, just because facts are narratively inflected or informed doesn’t
mean they’re not useful.
Before
I conclude, one final objection is worth pausing over: that even after sufficient theorization, certain
facts may remain that don’t fit the theoretical framework. Indeed, as Feyerabend contends, “no single
theory ever agrees with all the known facts in its domain.” The disharmony between theories and their
facts may signal the inconsistency of the theory, but it may also signal the
inconsistency of factual observation. In
either case, these contradictory facts exist, metaphorically speaking, as plot holes. Even if they don’t fit nicely into the theory
at hand, it’s because they don’t make narrative sense. So the takeaway isn’t that contradictory
facts reveal their theory-independent or preexistent nature, but merely that
our abilities to observe the world will, inevitably, turn up
inconsistencies. After all, we’re only
human.
This short essay began politically before turning scientific; but these two realms aren’t unrelated, and
the lessons of science have much to tell us about the assumptions we make in our
social and political conversations. It's often assumed that science is the bastion of hard facts and objectivity,
that it unveils the being of the world.
But the more we attend to the writings of scientists themselves, the
more we realize that science understands (or has come to understand) just how
narratively structured our knowledge is.
To return to Yiannopolous’s comment, privileging facts over narratives
or narratives over facts is a false dichotomy; those who privilege facts are privileging narratives, even if they
don’t recognize it. We have access to
facts, we discover facts; but they’re not out there in the world, waiting for
us. We build facts between us and the
world, as they accord to our narrative premises and the material entities that
make up reality. The world is out there,
in other words—the universe is out there—but our knowledge of it only emerges
through the stories that organize our lives.
Comments
Post a Comment